VennPoretsky’s Method: Geometrical Diagrams for Logical Problems

如果你也在线性代数linearalgebra这个学科遇到相关的难题,请随时添加vx号联系我们的代写客服。我们会为你提供专业的服务。 linearalgebra™长期致力于留学生网课服务,涵盖各个网络学科课程:金融学Finance,经济学Economics,数学Mathematics,会计Accounting,文学Literature,艺术Arts等等。除了网课全程托管外,linearalgebra™也可接受单独网课任务。无论遇到了什么网课困难,都能帮你完美解决!

0.48 The Geometrical Diagrams of VennPoretsky’s method may be looked upon as the perfection of the methods of Stanley Jevons and Venn.Conversely, it finds in them a geometrical and mechanical illustration, for Venn’s method is translated in geometrical diagrams which represent all the constituents, so that, in order to obtain the result, we need only strike out (by shading) those which are made to vanish by the data of the problem. For instance, the universe of three terms \(a,b,c\), represented by the unbounded plane,is divided by three simple closed contours into eight regions which represent the eight constituents (Fig. 1).To represent geometrically the data of Venn’s problem we must strike out the regions \(abc\), \(ab^{\prime}c^{\prime}\), \(a^{\prime}bc\) and \(a^{\prime}bc^{\prime}\); there will then remain the regions \(abc^{\prime}\), \(ab^{\prime}c\), \(a^{\prime}b^{\prime}c\), and \(a^{\prime}b^{\prime}c^{\prime}\) which will constitute the universe _relative to the problem_, being what Poretsky calls his _logical whole_ (Fig. 2). Then every class will be contained in this universe, which will give for each class the expression resulting from the data of the problem. Thus, simply by inspecting the diagram, we see that the region \(bc\) does not exist (being struck out); that the region \(b\) is reduced to \(ab^{\prime}c^{\prime}\) (hence to \(ab\)); that all \(a\) is \(b\) or \(c\), and so on.This diagrammatic method has, however, serious inconveniences as a method for solving logical problems. It does not show how the data are exhibited by canceling certain constituents, nor does it show how to combine the remaining constituents so as to obtain the consequences sought. In short, it serves only to exhibit one single step in the argument, namely the equation of the problem; it dispenses neither with the previous steps, _i.e._, “throan equation” and the transformation of the premises, nor with the subsequent steps, _i.e._, the combinations that lead to the various consequences. Hence it is of very little use, inasmuch as the constituents can be represented by algebraic symbols quite as well as by plane regions, and are much easier to deal with in this form. 0.49 The Logical Machine of JevonsIn order to make his diagrams more tractable, Venn proposed a mechanical device by which the plane regions to bestruck out could be lowered and caused to disappear. But Jevons invented a more complete mechanism, a sort of _logical piano_. The keyboard of this instrument was composed of keys indicating the various simple terms \((a,b,c,d)\), their negatives, and the signs \(+\) and \(=\). Another part of the instrument consisted of a panel with movable tablets on which were written all the combinations of simple terms and their negatives; that is, all the constituents of the universe of discourse. Instead of writing out the equalities which represent the premises, they are “played” on a keyboard like that of a typewriter. The result is that the constituents which vanish because of the premises disappear from the panel. When all the premises have been “played”, the panel shows only those constituents whose sum is equal to 1, that is, forms the universe with respect to the problem, its logical whole. This mechanical method has the advantage over Venn’s geometrical method of performing automatically the “throwing into an equation”, although the premises must first be expressed in the form of equalities; but it throws no more light than the geometrical method on the operations to be performed in order to draw the consequences from the data displayed on the panel. 0.50 Table of ConsequencesBut Poretsky’s method can be illustrated, better than by geometrical and mechanical devices, by the construction of a table which will exhibit directly all the consequences and all the causes of a given equality. (This table is relative to this equality and each equality requires a different table). Each table comprises the \(2^{n}\) classes that can be defined and distinguished in the universe of discourse of \(n\) terms. We know that an equality consists in the annulment of a certain number of these classes, viz., of those which have for constituents some of the constituents of its _logical zero_\(N\). Let \(m\) be the number of these latter constituents, then the number of the subclasses of \(N\) is \(2^{m}\) which, therefore, is the number of classes of the universe which vanish in consequence of the equality considered. Arrange them in a column commencing with 0 and ending with \(N\) (the two extremes). On the other hand, given any class at all, any preceding class may be added to it without altering its value, since by hypothesis they are null (in the problem under consideration). Consequently, by the data of the problem, each class is equal to \(2^{m}\) classes (including itself)

发表回复

您的电子邮箱地址不会被公开。 必填项已用 * 标注